9.1 Introduction
The Nobel Prize, often perceived as the pinnacle of objective recognition, is in fact the product of collective human judgment. Behind each award lies a process of deliberation, persuasion, and consensus — a microcosm of how societies determine truth and value.
This chapter examines the accuracy and fairness of Nobel decisions by analysing how voting operates within the committees, the philosophical limits of consensus, and the role of human subjectivity in defining “the greatest benefit to humankind.”
While the Nobel process strives for precision and impartiality, it ultimately demonstrates that even the most esteemed systems of evaluation are interpretive rather than infallible (Lundestad, 2017).
9.2 The Majority-Vote Principle
a. Procedural Foundation
Every Nobel Prize decision is finalised through majority voting within the relevant academy or committee. Once the Nobel Committee presents its shortlist, members of the awarding body vote to approve or reject candidates. Unanimity is desirable but not required.
In the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences and the Karolinska Institute, decisions are typically reached after rigorous discussion and successive ballots until a clear majority emerges (Crawford, 2016).
b. Rationale
The principle of majority voting reflects a philosophy of procedural legitimacy rather than empirical certainty. It presumes that the collective deliberation of experts yields the most defensible outcome — a form of epistemic democracy (Solomon, 2001).
Thus, the Nobel Prize does not claim absolute truth but consensus-based credibility, balancing diverse judgments within a framework of intellectual trust.
9.3 Consensus and the Sociology of Knowledge
As Bourdieu (1988) argues, institutions like the Nobel Academy function within a field of power where symbolic capital — reputation, authority, and expertise — defines influence. Votes therefore represent not only rational assessment but also social negotiation among peers.
Committee discussions often hinge on shared disciplinary paradigms, meaning that innovation outside established norms may face resistance until its legitimacy becomes undeniable. The delayed recognition of figures such as Einstein (1921) and Barbara McClintock (Medicine, 1983) exemplifies this tension between orthodoxy and originality (Pais, 1982).
The Nobel process thus illustrates the Weberian model of rational-legal authority: legitimacy emerges from rule-based procedure, not divine insight or populist acclaim (Weber, 1947).
9.4 The Challenge of Objectivity
a. The Problem of Measurement
Scientific accuracy, though central to Nobel evaluation, cannot fully eliminate interpretation. Discoveries are judged not only for factual correctness but also for impact, originality, and benefit — qualitative criteria requiring human judgment.
Even in Physics or Medicine, determining “the greatest benefit” is inherently normative. For instance, should an award prioritise theoretical elegance or practical application? The choice inevitably reflects the committee’s intellectual culture and moral worldview (Mirowski, 2020).
b. Literature and Peace: Subjectivity as Method
In Literature and Peace categories, objectivity is even more elusive. Aesthetic value and moral virtue cannot be measured scientifically; they rely on interpretive reasoning shaped by historical context. Consequently, these awards often mirror the moral imagination of their era — a reflection of collective conscience rather than absolute truth (Engdahl, 2012).
9.5 Case Studies of Human Judgment
a. The Case of Malala Yousafzai (Peace 2014)
Malala’s award, shared with Kailash Satyarthi, was a unanimous decision that transcended politics, celebrating moral courage. Yet critics questioned whether a teenager could embody sustainable peace leadership. The decision demonstrated symbolic judgment: peace as hope, not accomplishment (Lundestad, 2017).
b. Chemistry (2019): Goodenough, Whittingham, and Yoshino
Awarding three scientists for the development of the lithium-ion battery reflected committee adaptability to collective innovation — a recognition that modern discovery is collaborative, not solitary. This adjustment shows institutional learning from past omissions like Rosalind Franklin’s.
c. Literature (2016): Bob Dylan
The inclusion of a songwriter redefined literature’s boundaries, illustrating how consensus reinterprets categories rather than merely enforcing precedent.
These examples reveal that Nobel accuracy resides not in perfection but in self-corrective evolution.
9.6 The Role of Uncertainty
Every Nobel decision is made under conditions of epistemic uncertainty. Scientific discoveries may later be falsified; political heroes may falter; literary reputations may fade.
The committees mitigate this uncertainty through:
- External peer consultation (expert referees).
- Rigorous deliberation across multiple rounds.
- Historical conservatism — waiting for confirmation before awarding.
Yet uncertainty remains inherent. The Nobel Prize’s authority rests not on prediction but on faith in reasoned judgment — a belief that wisdom, though fallible, is achievable through dialogue (Crawford, 2016).
9.7 Voting as Ethical Ritual
Voting within the Nobel institutions is more than a procedural necessity; it is a ritual of moral affirmation. Each vote symbolises collective endorsement of values such as truth, justice, and progress.
The process embodies what sociologist Emile Durkheim termed collective effervescence — the moment when individual convictions fuse into communal belief (Durkheim, 1912). In this sense, Nobel voting is a secular act of faith in humanity’s capacity for fair judgment.
9.8 Philosophical Perspectives on Human Judgment
Philosophers of science and ethics emphasise that judgment is relational, not absolute.
- Kant (1788) viewed moral judgment as rooted in practical reason — rational but subjective.
- Arendt (1978) argued that judgment depends on enlarged mentality — the ability to think from others’ perspectives.
- Weber (1947) recognised that rational procedures must coexist with value pluralism in modern institutions.
The Nobel system, consciously or not, integrates these traditions: a procedural rationality guided by moral imagination. It accepts that consensus is not certainty, yet insists that collective deliberation is humanity’s best approximation of truth.
9.9 The Myth of Absolute Accuracy
Public fascination with the Nobel Prize often assumes an almost divine infallibility, as though the committees discern universal truth. However, historical hindsight reveals numerous errors of omission and judgment — figures overlooked, discoveries misattributed, and premature awards given.
These imperfections do not discredit the institution; rather, they expose its humanity. As Lundestad (2017) notes, “The Nobel system’s power lies not in perfection but in persistence.” It remains accurate not because it never errs, but because it consistently strives to align moral conviction with evidence and reason.
9.10 The Social Construction of Truth
Modern epistemology recognises that truth is socially constructed within institutional frameworks. The Nobel Prize thus functions as a truth-making institution — conferring legitimacy upon ideas through collective endorsement.
This sociological reality explains both its prestige and its controversies. To win a Nobel is to have one’s work canonised by the moral community of science or culture. The award’s accuracy lies in its ability to reflect the evolving consensus of civilisation, rather than an immutable standard.
9.11 Conclusion
The Nobel Prize system reveals the paradox of human judgment: it is both fallible and indispensable. Accuracy in the Nobel sense is not numerical precision but moral coherence — the ability to balance evidence, values, and collective responsibility.
The majority-vote principle does not ensure perfection, but it institutionalises fairness within limitation. By combining expertise with humility, the Nobel committees sustain the belief that reasoned consensus remains humanity’s most reliable guide.
Thus, the Nobel Prize’s authority endures not because it is infallible, but because it embodies faith in the integrity of human judgment itself.
References (Harvard Style)
- Arendt, H. (1978) The Life of the Mind, Vol. 1: Thinking. New York: Harcourt.
- Bourdieu, P. (1988) Homo Academicus. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
- Crawford, E. (2016) The Beginnings of the Nobel Institution: The Science Prizes, 1901–1915. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Durkheim, E. (1912) The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. Paris: Alcan.
- Engdahl, H. (2012) The Nobel Prize in Literature: A Century of Literary Achievement. Stockholm: Swedish Academy Publications.
- Kant, I. (1788) Critique of Practical Reason. Riga: Hartknoch.
- Lundestad, G. (2017) The Peace Prize: The Nobel Peace Prize and the Norwegian Nobel Committee through One Hundred Years. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Mirowski, P. (2020) Science-Mart: Privatizing American Science. Harvard University Press.
- Pais, A. (1982) Subtle Is the Lord: The Science and the Life of Albert Einstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Solomon, M. (2001) Social Empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Weber, M. (1947) The Theory of Social and Economic Organization. New York: Free Press.